Social Value

Chapter 1: Problem and Plan of Procedure

Benjamin McAlester Anderson Jr.

Table of Contents | Next | Previous

RECENT economic literature has had much to say about "social value." The conception, while not entirely new,[1] has become important only of late years, chiefly through the influence of Professor J. B. Clark, who first set it forth in his article in The New Englander in 1881 (since reproduced as the chapter on the theory of value in his Philosophy of Wealth). The conception has been found attractive by many other American


(4) writers, however, and has become familiar in many text-books, and in periodical literature. Among those who have used the conception may be named: Professors Seligman., Bullock, Kinley, Merriam, Ross, and C. A. Tuttle.[2] Gabriel Tarde, the brilliant French sociologist, has independently developed a social value doctrine, different in many respects from that of the Americans named, which we shall later have occasion to consider.[3]

In its most definite form, the theory asserts that the value of an economic good is determined by, and precisely accords with, the marginal utility of the good to society, considered as a unitary organism. Professor Clark, as is well known, makes use of the analysis of diminishing utility in an individual's consumption of goods in much the same fashion that Jevons does, but while Jevons makes this simply a step in the analysis of market ratios of exchanges, Professor Clark treats it as analogical, representing in


(5) parvo what society does, as an organic whole, on a bigger scale.[4]

The precise relation of social value to social marginal utility is variously stated by the writers named: for Professor Clark, value is the measure of effective, or marginal, utility;[5] for Professor Seligman, social value is the expression of social marginal utility ;[6] for Professors Ross, Merriam, and Kinley, value is that social marginal utility itself.[7] These statements are more different in words than in ideas, though some significance is to be attached to Professor Seligman's formulation, as will later appear.

This conception is a bold one. It has, moreover, never been adequately developed or criticized. Its friends have found it a convenient and useful working hypothesis, and Professor Clark, especially, has built a great system upon it, but, with the exception of an article in the Yale Review of 1892,[8] has made no serious efforts, either to make clear its full meaning, or to vindicate it except that, of course, his whole system may be considered such a vindication. Professor Seligman, in an article in the Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. XV, and also in his Principles of Economics, has espoused the conception, and has shown how, assuming its truth, a great many


(6) antagonistic theories may be harmonized; but he, also, has failed to treat it with that detail which full demonstration requires. In particular, he has omitted a treatment of the problem of the relation between the value of a good for the individual and for society, and the relation between individual and social marginal utility.[9] The most searching investigation of the theory has come from unfriendly critics, among whom may be especially named Professor H. J. Davenport, and Professor J. Schumpeter of Vienna. [10]

For the purposes of this discussion, Professor Clark will be considered as the representative of


(7) the Social Value School, for the most part, though attention will be given to some of the other writers named as well. It is worth while, consequently, to make clear at this point the relation between Professor Clark and the Austrian School, with which he is sometimes associated by economic writers. His extensive use of the marginal principle, his use of the term, "utility," and his deduction of value from utility, seem to place him at one with them. Professor Clark has pointed out, however, in the preface to the second edition of his Philosophy of Wealth, that his theory is to be distinguished from that of Jevons by "the analysis of the part played by society as an organic whole in the valuing processes of the market." And the Austrians, for their part, have rejected the conception that value and social marginal utility coincide, or that society, as an organic whole, puts a value on goods. Thus, Bohm-Bawerk:

Man pflegt den objektiven Tauschwert im Gegensatz zu dem auf individuellen Schätzungen beruhenden subjektiven Wert häufig auch als den volkswirtschaftlichen Wert der Güter zu bezeichnen. Ich halte diesen Gebrauch für nicht empfehlenswert. Zwar wenn man durch ihn nichts anders hervorheben wollte, als dass diese Gestalt des Wertes nur in der Gesellschaft und durch die Gesellschaft hervortreten könne, dass er also das volks- und sozialwirtschaftliehe Wertphänomen per eminentiam sei, so wäre dagegen nichts zu erinnern. Gewöhnlich mischt sich aber mit jener Benennung auch die Vorstellung, dass der Tauschwert der Wert sei, den ein Gut für die Volkswirtschaft habe. Man deutet ihn als ein über den subjektiven Urteilen der einzelnen stehendes Urteil der Gesellschaft, welche Bedeutung ein Gut für sie im ganzen habe; gewissermassen als


(8) Werturteil einer objektiven höheren Instanz. Dies ist irreführend.[11]

Equally emphatic is Wieser:


The ordinary conception, which makes price the social estimate put upon goods, has to the superficial judgment the attraction of simplicity. A good A whose market price is £100 is not only ten times as dear as B whose market price is no, but it is also absolutely and for every one ten times as valuable. In our conception the matter is much more complicated. . . . Price alone forms no basis whatever for an estimate of the economic importance of the goods. We must go further and find out their relation to wants. But this relation to wants can only be realised and measured individually. . . . And the question how it is possible to unite those divergent individual valuations into one social valuation, is one that cannot be answered quite so easily as those imagine who are rash enough to conclude that price represents the social estimate of value.[12]

Sax, likewise, expresses his dissent:

Da für die exaete Forschung die Psyche einer fabelhaften Collectiv-Persönlichkeit nicht existirt, so kann der Ausgangspunkt unserer Untersuchung auch wieder nur der Individualwerth seen.[13]

Whatever the worth of the conception of social value, it is not the same as the Austrian theory. It is proper to remark here that these strictures of the Austrian writers are probably directed, not against Professor Clark, but rather against the social use-value concept as it had appeared in Germany, in the writings, say, of Rodbertus, and


(9) of Adolph Wagner, who accepts Rodbertus' notion.[14]

It may be well, at the outset, for the writer to define his own position briefly. We shall find the notion of social marginal utility, and the companion notion of social marginal cost (considering the latter as a "real cost," or pain-abstinence cost, concept), unsatisfactory and unilluminating. Social marginal utility, as a determinant of value, cannot be the marginal utility of a good to some particular individual who stands out as the marginal individual in society, nor can it be an average of individual marginal utilities, nor a sum of individual marginal utilities, nor any other possible arithmetical combination of individual marginal utilities, if our conclusions are true. For the term, social marginal utility, we can find only a vague, analogical meaning, if any at all, unless we identify it outright with social value, in which case it is a superfluous term, which itself not only explains nothing, but rather presents complications which call for explanation. We shall find no use for the social utility concept in our analysis. On the other hand, we shall find the conception of social value a necessity for the validation of economic analysis, and a conception which present-day psychological and sociological theory abundantly warrant us in accepting.

I do not desire, at the outset of a comparatively short book, to anticipate my arguments in detail, but a statement of the plan of procedure


(10) may aid the exposition somewhat. I shall first, through an examination of the logical necessities of economic theory, and of the function of the value concept in economics, set up certain logical and formal qualifications for an adequate value concept. Then I shall examine the efforts made by current theories of value to attain such a value concept, by means of the elements of individual utilities, individual costs, or combinations of the two, and show that such procedure gets into invincible logical difficulties. We shall find the source of these difficulties in the faulty epistemology, psychology, and sociology which constitute the avowed or implicit presuppositions of the economic theory of to-day. Criticizing these faulty presuppositions, we shall endeavor to reconstruct them in the light of later epistemological, psychological, and sociological doctrine, and then, on the basis of the new presuppositions, we shall endeavor to develop a truly organic doctrine of social value, and to link it with what seems valuable - that is to say, the greater part - in the economic theory of to-day.

Notes

  1. The value concept of Marx is not, strictly speaking, a social value concept. Cf. Pareto, V., Cours d'Economie Politique, vol. i, p. 32. Rodbertus, however, has a doctrine of social use value, based on the organic conception of society. " Nemlich so: es gibt nur Eine Art Werth und das ist der Gebrauchswerth.... Aber dieser Eine Gebrauchswerth ist entweder individueller Gebrauchswerth oder socialer Gebrauchswerth.... Der zweite ist der Gebrauchswerth, den ein aus vielen individuellen Organismen bestehender socialer Organismus hat. . . . Damit glaube ich also bewiesen zu haben, dass der Tauschwerth nur der historische Um- und Anhang des socialen Gebrauchswerths aus einer bestimmten Geschichtsperiode ist. Indem man also dem Gebrauchswerth einen Tauschwerth als logischen Gegensatz gegenüber stellt, stellt man zu einem logischen Begriff einen historischen Begriff in logischem Gegensatz, was logisch nicht angeht." From a letter to Adolph Wagner, published by Wagner in the Zeitschrift fur die Gesammte Statitswissenschaft, 1878, pp. 223-34. Wagner indicates his approval of this concept, though he makes little Use Of it. in his Grundlegung der politischen Oekonomie, Leipzig, 1991, PP. 329-30. Ingram, in his History of Political Economy (New York, 1888), although he takes no account of social value theories of other writers, suggests one of his own - which is, however, a vague one, mixing technoIogical, ethical, and economic categories. See p. 241.
  2. Seligman, E. R. A., Principles of Economics, New York, 1905, especially pp. 179-82 and 192-93. Bullock, C. J., Introduction to the Study of Economics, especially pp. 162--64. There is no attempt at a psychological treatment in this work, and no clear statement of the meaning of the concept, social. Kinley, David, Money, New York, 1904, pp. 125-26. Ile social value conception runs through the book. Merriam, L. S., "The Theory of Final Utility in its Relation to Money and the Standard of Deferred Payments," Annals of the American Academy, vol. III; "Money as a Measure of Value," ibid., vol. IV; an unfinished study in the same volume, pp. 969-72. described by Professor J. B. Clark. Ross, E. A., " The Standard of Deferred Payments," ibid., vol. III; "Ile Total Utility Standard of Deferred Payments," ibid.. vol. IV. These articles by Professors Ross and Merriam were- written in the course of an interesting controversy versy between the gentlemen named. Tuttle, C. A., "The Wealth Concept," ibid., vol. I; "The Fundamental Economic Principle," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1901.
  3. See chapter XII.
  4. See especially Professor Clark's Essentials of Economic Theory, New York, 1907, pp. 41-42.
  5. See especially The Philosophy of Wealth, 1892 ed., pp. 73-74.
  6. Principles, pp. 179-82.
  7. The general references for Ross and Merriam have been given supra Cf. P. 62 of Dean Kinley's Money.
  8. "Ultimate Standard of Value." This article is substantially the same an chap. XXIV of The Distribution of Wealth, New York. 1899.
  9. In his discussion of social value in the Principles, Professor Seligman modifies a statement made in his article, "Social Elements in the Theory of Value " (Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. XV). The two discussions are parallel in part. the former being based upon the latter. The passage quoted is from the Q. J. E. article, pp. 323-324. The same passage is essentially reproduced in the Principles (first edition, p. 180), with the exception of the passages in italics: "I not only measure the relative satisfaction that I can get from apples or nuts, but the quantity of apples I can get for the nuts depends upon the relative estimate put upon them by the rest of society. Some individuals may prize a commodity a little more, some a little less; but its real value is the average estimate, the estimate of what society thinks it is worth. If an apple is worth twice as much as a nut, it is only because the community, after comparing and averaging individual preferences," etc. The conception of social value as an average of individual values is withdrawn in the second treatment, and no substitute is offered for it.
  10. Davenport, "Seligman, 'Social Value,"' Journal of Pol. Econ., 1906; Value and Distribution, Chicago. 1908. This last work reproduces, in abridged form, the article on Professor Seligman, in a footnote, pp. 444 et seq. Schumpeter, "On the Concept of Social Value," Q. J. E., Feb., 1909; "Die neuere Wirtschaftslehre in den Vereinigten Staaten, " Jahrbuch fur Gesetzgebung, Verwaltung und Volkswirtschaft im Deutschen Reich, 1010, pp. 013 el seq. In the last-named article (p. 925, n.) Professor Schumpeter indicates that his objection to the social value concept relates not so much to the question of fact as to the question of method. The English article in the Quarterly Journal contains Schumpeter's fullest treatment of the topic.
  11. Böhm-Bawerk, Grundzuge der Theorie des wirtschaftlichen Guter-werk Conrad's Jahrbucher, N. F., Bd. XIII, 1886, p. 478.
  12. Natural Value, p. 52, n.
  13. Sax, Emil, Grundlegung der theoretischen Staatswirtschaft, Vienna, 1887, p. 249.
  14. See supra, p. 3, note 1.

Valid HTML 4.01 Strict Valid CSS2